Programme :
James Higginbotham ; Departments of Linguistics and Philosophy, University of Southern California : Rules of Use
Joëlle Proust, Institut Jean Nicod, CNRS, Paris ; Max Planck Institute for Evolutionary, Anthropology, Leipzig
François Recanati, Institut Jean Nicod, CNRS, Paris
Jérôme Dokic, Institut Jean Nicod, Paris,EHESS, Paris
Metacognition of the first person
Philippe Schlenker, Institut Jean-Nicod, CNRS, Paris ; Department of Linguistics, University of California, Los Angeles
Alexandre Billon, Institut Jean-Nicod, CNRS, Paris/ CREA, Ecole Polytechnique, Paris ; Marie Guillot, Institut Jean-Nicod, Paris, EHESS, Paris : Could first-personal thoughts be self-referential ?
The aim of the conference is to shed light on the complex relationship between the salient epistemic properties of egology - or what we may call, after Lewis 1979, ’de se thoughts’ - and the putative existence and nature of an underlying self-representational structure.
Egocentric thoughts, like those expressed by a subject when she declares « I wish a woman could win the election » or « I see a canary », can be conveniently singled out in terms of their specific epistemic properties. These thoughts are reputed to be invulnerable to certain forms of error : they display what Shoemaker has famously called « immunity to error through misidentification », as well as, in core cases, immunity to error through misascription of properties. Other remarkable epistemic features of I-thoughts include their apparent groundlessness, or exemption from the need of an epistemic justification, the privilege of first-personal access to such thoughts, and the subsequent authority attached to first-personal reports on them.
Traditionally, the philosophy of mind has explored two antagonist paths to account for these peculiarities. The divergence between these two options rests on the stance taken up on the question as to whether such de se contents involve self-representation, in the two-fold sense of self-reference (a representation of the subject in her own thoughts) and token-reflexivity (a representation of occurrent thoughts, in part or in totality, within their own content).
The first option stems from a positive answer to this question. According to a number of authors, who appeal to a plausible principle of isomorphism between I-thoughts and first-personal utterances, the well-documented asymmetry between first- and third-personal mental states is due to the peculiar way in which a subject is represented in her own thoughts in the first case. In view of avoiding positing a direct acquaintance with one’s own self, or alternatively a sui generis « mode of presentation » through which the thinker, and she only, could refer to herself, a number of philosophers have recently proposed to construe type-egocentric thoughts as involving a token-reflexive structure, whereby the thinker is indirectly represented in her own (occurring) thoughts through the specific relation she has with these token-thoughts, whose representation contribute a constituent to their own content. Contemporary accounts pertaining to this strategy include J. Perry’s articles from the 1990s, recent suggestions from M. Garcia-Carpintero, as well as J. Higginbotham’s 2003 article « Remembering, Imagining, and the First Person », which argues that a token-, or rather event-reflexive structure, governed by complex anaphoric relations, may underlie and explain the peculiar semantic and epistemic behavior of I-thoughts, at least in cases where they are embedded within the scope of higher-order attitudes.
The second option, whose origin could be traced back to Wittgenstein 1953 and Anscombe 1975, consists in an endeavor to explain the epistemic peculiarities of I-thoughts by the absence of self-representation. As Perry 1993/2000 states it, one’s basic knowledge of oneself can be considered as « intrinsically selfless ». According to accounts that are sympathetic to this view, the content of fundamental I-thoughts, like those involved in perception and action, is a neutral proposition which concerns, instead of being about, the thinker. The latter’s identity being, so to speak, the default value of the point of origin defining the orientation of the perceptual framework, it imposes such a strong architectural constraint on one’s mental life that representing oneself would be, in many cases, redundant and needlessly costly in terms of cognitive investment. On the other hand, if there is, in one’s most primitive egocentric mental states at least, no self-representation, hence no need to identify oneself as such in order to pick oneself out correctly, then there is a fortiori no room for any misidentification. All the other, related epistemic privileges of the first-person perspective can then be taken to follow from this basic assumption. Contemporary uses of this intuition include, in the philosophy of cognition, contextualist treatments of egocentricity in the theoretical framework of embodied and situated cognition, as recently advocated, among others, by J. Dokic’s 2003 and forthcoming papers. In the philosophy of mind and language, similar considerations could be arguably attributed to F. Recanati in his forthcoming book on perspectival thought. Setting his account of first-personal contents within the framework of a moderate semantic relativism, Recanati analyzes the content of core cases of I-thoughts in the light of a distinction between two distinct components, a context-sensitive propositional structure, which he calls the ’lekton’, and a wide context which provides a cluster of points of evaluation in addition to the world parameter, including a subject, relative to which the lekton is truth-evaluated.
Faced with the alternative of explaining the peculiarities of de se thoughts by invoking either the nature and structure of an underlying self-representation, or the radical absence of such a mechanism, one may want to weigh up the advantages and difficulties involved by each side of the dilemma.
Contextualist theories are supported by plausible considerations of cognitive economy, since they dispense with positing complex representations behind egocentric mental states. However, one of the challenges to such theories lies in the question as to whether they can give a convincing account of the relationship between basic, primitive egocentric thoughts, like those involved in perception and action, and more complex I-thoughts to which we give verbal expression using explicit markers of the first person – e.g. first-personal reports of embedded attitudes like (1) « I remember wishing you were dead » - and which unquestionably involve self-representation. The latter share with basic egocentric mental states all the epistemic peculiarities that single out de se thoughts, but it is difficult to see how the contextualist explanation could be generalized to their more complex semantic behavior. In particular, the anaphoric structure of an example like (1), in which the elided subject of the gerundive clause has to be interpreted as referring back to the same individual as the subject of the embedding verb, seems to require the prior introduction of a marker of discourse corresponding to the said subject, hence a self-representational underlying structure.
Self-representational theories may seem, prima facie, more apt to give a unified account of the epistemic peculiarities attached to de se thoughts, but they can also be addressed a number of objections. S. Predelli 2006 has thus pointed out that they are exposed to the risk of an uncontrolled ontological proliferation. Moreover, self-representational theories must justify the additional cognitive cost their complexity involves, and demonstrate their compatibility with the presence of metacognitional, hence egocentric mental states in animals and yound children. As Proust forthcoming convincingly shows, there are principled reasons to think that metacognition, especially in the most primitive cases, does not rest on self-directed metarepresentational capacities. Could self-representational theories of de se thought account for the fact that even systems lacking the capacity to represent themselves explicitly show self-directed metacognitional aptitudes ?
Castañeda, H.-N. 1966, « ‘He’ : A Study in the Logic of Self-Consciousness », Ratio 8, 130-157.
Dokic, J. forthcoming. « La dernière personne : sur la critique de l’égologie cognitive dans Le complément de sujet de Vincent Descombes ».
Dokic, J. 2003a. "The Sense of Ownership : An Analogy between Sensation and Action", in N. Eilan et J. Roessler (eds), Agency and Self-Awareness. Issues in Philosophy and Psychology, Oxford, Clarendon Press, p. 321-344.
Dokic, J. 2003b. "L’identification de soi, entre savoir-faire et introspection", in S. Chauvier (ed.), Gareth Evans, Cahiers de philosophie de l’Université de Caen, n° 40-41 p 45-64.
Harman, G. 2006,.« Self-Reflexive Thoughts », Philosophical Issues 16 (2006) : 334-45.
Higginbotham, J. 2003. « Remembering, Imagining, and the First Person », in Alex Barber (ed.), Epistemology of Language. Oxford : Oxford University Press. pp. 496-533.
Higginbotham, J. 1995, « Tensed Thoughts », Mind and Language vol. 10 n°3, 226-249.
Kaplan, D. 1990. « Thoughts on Demonstratives », in P. Yourgrau (ed.), Demonstratives. OUP.
Lewis, D. 1979, « Attitudes, De Dicto and De Se », Philosophical Review 88 : 513-543 ; repris dans Philosophical Papers, vol. I, New York : OUP, 1983.
Millikan, R. 2001. « The Myth of Mental Indexicals », in Self-Reference and Self-Awareness, Brook, Andrew and Richard C. DeVidi (ed.), 2001, 163–177.
Perry, J. 1997. « Reflexivity, Indexicality and Names », in Direct Reference, Indexicality and Proposition Attitudes, ed. W. Kunne, M. Anduschus and A. Newen, Stanford : CSLI, CUP, 1997.
Perry, J. 1998. ”Indexicals, Contexts and Unarticulated Constituents”, in Proceedings of the 1995 CSLI-Amsterdam LLC Conference, Stanford : CSLI Publications.
Perry, J. 1997. ”Myself and I” in M. Stamm ed., Philosophie in Syntetischer Absicht, Stuttgart : Klett-Cotta, 1998, pp. 83-103.
Predelli, S. 2006. ”The Problem with Token-Reflexivity”, Synthese 148 (1) 5-29.
Proust, J. forthcoming. ”Metacognition and Metarepresentation : Is a self-directed theory of the mind a precondition for metacognition ?”, Synthese, 2007.
Proust, J. 2003. ”Thinking of Oneself as the Same”, Consciousness and Cognition, 2003, 12, 4, 495-509.
Proust, J. 2000. ”Les conditions de la connaissance de soi”, in Philosophiques 27, 1, 2000, 161-186.
Recanati, F. forthcoming. Perspectival Thought. A Plea for (Moderate) Relativism. Prepublication on the website www.institunicod.fr.
Recanati, F. 2005. ”Loana dans le métro. Remarques sur l’indexicalité mentale”, in S. Bourgeois-Gironde, ed., Les formes de l’indexicalité, Paris, Editions rue d’Ulm, pp. 19-34.
Schlenker, P. forthcoming. ”The Elimination of Self-Reference (Generalized Yablo-Series and the Theory of Truth)”, accepted for publication in the Journal of Philosophical Logic .
Schlenker, P. 2003. « A Plea for Monsters », Linguistics and Philosophy 26 : 29-120.